

He was a republican in holding to the neoclassical, seventeenth-century English commonwealth idea that for the preservation of public liberty a certain virtue in the people was still necessary (p. He was a liberal in subscribing to the social contract theory of the origins of government and the idea that the end of government is to protect the liberty and property rights of individuals. Madison, acknowledged in recent scholarship as the most penetrating and representative political thinker among the authors of the Constitution, did not shift from classical republicanism to liberalism in the constitution-making phase of the Revolution, as has been thought. Revolutionary principles, Banning writes, always meant both firm securities for private rights and the perpetuation of a form of government that derived entirely from, and remained responsive to, the body of an equal people (p. Banning stated that the fundamental premise of a properly balanced republican constitutionalism was the existence of self-interested individuals and groups.īannings study of Madison presents the results of a fresh examination of the sources based on a deeper understanding of what is now generally recognized as the liberal republican political philosophy of the American Revolution. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1988, p. In a 1988 essay Banning distanced himself from republican ideological orthodoxy in arguing that republican virtue did not, in essence, mean self-surrender, but rather vigorous assertions of the self within a context of communal consciousness and a willingness to live by the communitys decisions (Some Second Thoughts on Virtue and the Course of Revolutionary Thinking, in Conceptual Change and the Constitution, edited by Terence Ball and J.G.A. The direction of Bannings work is particularly important in view of his reputation as a leading exponent of the republican-ideology interpretation of early American constitutionalism.

Banning shifts the focus of study from the republicanism versus liberalism problem that has preoccupied historians for a generation, to the older and more fundamental issue of centralization versus states rights. Lance Bannings new book on the political and constitutional thought of James Madison in the American founding signals this intellectual development in historical scholarship. Most constitutional and legal historians have not required instruction on this point, but the idea of bringing the states back in might serve as a useful description of recent developments in constitutional jurisprudence that reflect the exhaustion of nationalism as a creative intellectual and political force.

Their point, a methodological one, is that formal institutions of government really do exist and have a significant impact on the course of political events. In recent years some historical sociologists, critical of the tendency of Marxist and other forms of grand social theory to disregard empirical evidence, have urged a strategy of bringing the state back in to the study of politics.
